The Federalism Project

American Enterprise Institute

Draft: Do not cite without permission

Federalism Values and Foreign Relations

Michael S. Greve*

In attacking the orthodox view of an exclusive, incontestable federal monopoly over foreign relations, Edward T. Swaine argues, revisionist scholars have so far failed to address, “at any length,” the “ultimate challenge” of “locating new functions and values for the states in a globalized, yet federal, world.”[1]  Both the criticism and the underlying intuition strike me as substantially correct.  The revisionist attempt to rehabilitate federalism and the states presupposes that federalism serves some important value or values. In light of the momentous changes wrought by a global, interconnected world, those values cannot simply be assumed; they have to be identified and defended.

That said, Swaine’s proposed search for “new functions and values” seems needlessly ambitious.  The central dynamics of globalization—increased international mobility of capital and labor, international treaty arrangements that reach deep into formerly domestic affairs, the operation of domestic corporations on a global scale and, conversely, of foreign corporations in home state markets--do of course compel a re-thinking of domestic arrangements.  Still, it seems likely that the “new” federalism values and functions will be extensions and modifications of the old ones.  The real question is whether a globalized world renders familiar features of federalism more, or less, functional and valuable.

One set of traditional federalism values that might be thought to gain increased currency in a globalized world revolves around political participation.  States have traditionally been viewed as being “closer to the people” than the national government.  Now that the forces and institutions that shape our lives are even more distant, alien, and unresponsive, it has become all the more important to cultivate and protect local attachments, mores, policies, and voices.[2]  An enhanced role for the states in international affairs, on issues that might affect their citizens, could improve the recognition and representation of local values, interests, and concerns.

An alternative set of traditional federalism values centers around the benefits of jurisdictional diversity and competition.  Jurisdictional diversity makes it possible to accommodate a wider range of citizen-consumer preferences, more of the time.  Competition among governments, coupled with then option of “exit” for dissatisfied citizens and businesses, disciplines interest-group politics.  On this view, federalism merits preservation (or restoration) against national and international arrangements alike, for substantially the same reasons.  Federalism merits a firm defense especially now that international arrangements provide revenue-hungry governments and rent-seeking interest groups with enhanced opportunities to trump the salutary, disciplining force of jurisdictional competition.

Space constraints mercifully preclude anything resembling the full development of these two lines of argument and their implications for constitutional law and doctrine.  The remainder of this article sketches the basic intuitions and presumptions that might inform a future analysis.

I strongly suspect that the “local participation” story is ultimately implausible.  As an initial matter, the successful cultivation of local attachments does not appear to correspond, in any systematic way, to constitutional federalism arrangements.  (It seems to work better in centralized France than in some federalist countries.)  Even if that assessment is mistaken, the notion that local politics and participation might compensate for global alienation and dislocations is open to serious question.  On some issues, more leeway for state governments would arguably help to counter civic alienation.  By way of prominent example, the citizens of Massachusetts might feel better about themselves and their role in the world if they were permitted to register their disapproval of the government of Burma and corporations that deal with the SLORC (or whatever that country and its junta may now be called).[3]  For the most part, however, globalization’s discontents arise from sources that are beyond the reach of state governments, and citizens’ sense of having lost control over some aspects of their lives cannot easily be compensated through more participation in some other venue and walk of life.  Citizens whose 401(k) investments take a nose dive, courtesy of Indonesian kleptocrats or the International Monetary Fund, are unlikely to be mollified by opportunities for meaningful civic involvement on or with the Richmond city council or the Roanoke school board.     

The diversity-and-competition story, in contrast, seems quite compelling.  Federalism’s point, this version of the story has it, is not to give citizens and their state and local governments a greater voice; rather, federalism’s point is to preserve citizens’ choice among competing sovereigns and their right to exit oppressive jurisdictions—by voting with their feet, their modems, and their pocketbooks.  Modern technologies have greatly reduced the costs of exercising exit rights, thus rendering their disciplining force much more powerful.  That is why jurisdictional competition is a much more salient and attractive notion now than it was, say, in the nineteenth century.

This intuition is somewhat at odds with the conventional globalization story. Increased international complexity and interdependence are commonly taken to entail (a) greater cultural and economic homogeneity; (b) greater interdependence and complexity, especially in economic and environmental matters; and (c) and accordingly, a substantially greater need for global cooperation and economic and environmental management (through international organizations, or agreements, or some other means).  Excellent theoretical and practical reasons, however, provide ample cause for skepticism about the conventional move from (b) to (c)—that is, the notion that increased complexity and interdependence necessitate more central political intervention.  

Scholars in the tradition of Friedrich A. Hayek are bound to argue that increased complexity, on a larger scale, is a powerful argument against political centralization, not for it.[4]  Since the rigidities, inefficiencies, and unintended consequences of government regulation increase with the scale and complexity of the regulated subject-matter, the idea of managing the world as a global commons is absurd.  By the same token, increased international interdependence arguably renders political borders more rather than less important.  The thought (or the slogan) of a “world without borders” becomes rather unappealing, once one recognizes that a world without borders is a world without exits.  Free citizens and free markets need exits.  The world needs no tax “harmonization”; it needs and wants the tax havens the OECD is trying to wipe out.[5]

Admittedly, this line of argument cuts primarily in favor of diversity and competition among countries or nation-states, and only secondarily and incidentally for domestic federalism.  Some of those secondary considerations, however, are quite persuasive. 

(a)    More competition is better.  So, for example, international competition between the United States and foreign countries for the location of automobile plants is a good thing.  Even better, however, if South Carolina can compete with Ohio, Michigan, Canada, and the rest of the world by offering BMW a deep sea port, right-to-work laws, and state troopers who care little about drivers who mistake the interstate highway system near Spartanburg for the Autobahn.

(b)   Domestic federalism may set precedents or provide competitive models that can be scaled internationally.  For example, successful and highly efficient state competition for corporate chartering[6] demonstrates why international agreements on corporate chartering should probably take the form of reciprocal recognition of domestic charters, rather than harmonizing standards.  For another example, successful federalist regulation of internet privacy and consumer marketing information here in the United States might well show that appropriate choice-of-law and contractual rules are preferable to an international regulatory “privacy” cartel.[7]

(c)    A robust federalism may help to protect domestic diversity and competition against efforts to utilize international agreements as a means of bringing domestic “outlier” states in line with the aspirations of national elites and interest groups.  The menace of international “policy laundering” is particularly acute in Europe, where regions rightly suspect that national policy elites are deliberately using the presumed demand for European integration as a means of undermining regional autonomy.  The same concern, however, also applies in the United States, where the 2000 presidential election provided fresh evidence of a pronounced cultural divide that, to a remarkable extent, maps state lines.  Most of the states that elected President George W. Bush—the Republican “sea of red” on the electoral map—administer the death penalty, some of them to minors.  None permit homosexual unions.  Many lack hate speech laws and “comparable worth” statutes.  All of them lack much of the stuff that is now the warp and woof of international human rights covenants and conventions.  The Democratic states, on average, conform more thoroughly to emerging international norms, and perhaps they are more enlightened.  Above a threshold of truly universal human rights guarantees, however (which all of the American states meet), citizen choice and jurisdictional diversity are vastly preferable to international regimentation.

What follows from competitive federalism values and priorities at the level of constitutional doctrine?  Competitive federalism demands firm barriers against the imposition of centralizing international norms (whether through treaties, customary international law, or some other vehicle) on the states.  Conversely, though somewhat less obviously, it implies fairly tight and, if you will, “nationalist” restrictions on the states’ participation in international politics and against the extra-territorial projection of state sovereignty outside the ordinary, domestic channels of political participation.[8]

The task of translating these general presumptions into constitutional doctrine ought to be approached with considerable caution.  First, as Swaine’s observes, foreign affairs federalism’s constitutional context is poorly understood.[9]  Extending that observation, one must say that many of federalism’s constitutional doctrines and their basic applications are poorly developed and understood even in the domestic context. Far from confounding a well-settled body of doctrine and precedent, then, foreign affairs issues add another layer of confusion.  Second, the preservation (or, more precisely in the contemporary context, the restoration) of a competitive, “market-preserving” federalism is a very difficult endeavor.[10]  It is not simply a matter of appropriate legal, constitutional arrangements but rather involves basic questions of social stratification, interest group constellations and alignments, and the range and intensity of social, ideological, and ethnic conflict.[11] 

One can say with some confidence, though, that competitive federalism requires, as a necessary condition, the existence of constitutional, judicially enforceable (and politically tenable) limitations on the national government’s powers.  Sans such limitations, the national government will consistently, and successfully, accede to insistent demands for the suppression of state competition.  This problem, of course, marks the constitutional battle ground of “enumerated powers” and, in particular, the Article I powers that, when interpreted with suitable generosity, enable Congress to circumvent the limitations that the constitutional text seems to impose—prominently, the Spending Clause, the Commerce Clause, and, according to the traditional view, the treaty power.[12]

At this particular front, foreign affairs federalism issues actually seem somewhat more manageable, both as a doctrinal and as a practical matter, than the corresponding domestic issues.  Revisionists have urged a reconsideration of the doctrine of Missouri v. Holland.[13]  At the limit, the revisionist view pushes toward a set of rules that preclude the national government from doing to the states through international arrangements what it may not do to them under its domestic enumerated powers.  The historical, textual, and conceptual arguments for this view are substantially better developed, and to my mind more persuasive, than are analogous, embryonic attempts to develop a coherent theory that would limit congressional power under the Spending Clause.[14]  As a practical matter, moreover, it seems quite feasible to defend the principle that the national government may not “internationalize” its way around domestic constitutional constraints.  In contrast, the analogous principle that Congress may not spend its way around those constraints is, notwithstanding its honorable Madisonian origin and pedigree, a political impossibility.  Spending its way around constitutional limitations is what Congress does for a living, and one cannot easily articulate a line that would circumscribe that power without laying waste to the entire administrative state.

In addition to enforceable limitations on the national government’s authority, a federalism that values jurisdictional diversity and competition requires doctrines that curtail both state protectionism and the extraterritorial projection of state sovereignty.    Competitive federalism’s central problem is not the threat of national impositions and “unfunded mandates” on states but rather the states’ demand for national intervention.[15]  Progressive, intervention-minded states face the constant challenge of accommodating powerful domestic interest groups. They seek to meet that challenge by exporting the costs of their regulatory regimes—and by insisting on national “harmonization.”  These strategies, when successful, may in some sense enhance “participatory” federalism values.  But they undermine competitive federalism.

While these considerations apply to federalism in general (prior to and independent from any globalization and foreign affairs complications), they supply an additional reason (additional, that is, to the traditional “one voice” rationale for a federal foreign affairs monopoly) to be skeptical of larger state role in international affairs.  If the recent past is prologue, ‘tis only a matter of time before the National Governors Association or the Union of Concerned States shows up at an international confab to lobby alongside the usual interest group claimants for some international labor or environmental agreement, the better to use that commitment as a means of leveraging the states’ demands in Washington, D.C.[16] Of course (one might object), the states already possess ample opportunities and institutional channels to press their demands for anti-competitive national legislation.  That, though, is precisely the point:  there being numerous domestic, constitutionally envisioned means through which intervention-minded states may seek to have their way, it seems ill-advised to provide them with an additional, international, extra-constitutional platform.[17] 

At the constitutional level, this line of thought counsels adherence to some “nationalist” legal doctrines that we have, such as a fairly rigid interpretation of the foreign compacts clause and a per se prohibition against facially discriminatory state action under the commerce clause, foreign and domestic.  At the same time, competitive foreign affairs federalism should prompt more careful thought about doctrines that we currently lack—prominently, coherent rules and doctrines concerning state “exports” of regulatory and tax burdens, from products liability law to the taxation of interstate transactions.  In this area of federalism’s horizontal dimensions, constitutional and sub-constitutional rules (such as conflicts and choice of law) are in considerable disrepair—in part, because the policing of interstate regulatory aggression has been viewed as principally a congressional obligation; in other part, because the post-New Deal judiciary believed that enforceable limits on state “experiments” that impose costs on outside parties would leave insufficient room for interest group politics.            

It should therefore come as no surprise that international complaints over U.S. domestic, state-based trade distortions have increasingly targeted state regulatory aggressions (as distinct from protectionism)—state unitary taxation of foreign-based multinational corporations;[18] more recently, Mississippi’s tort law and California’s fuel additive regulations.[19]  The time may have come to re-think the extant, substantive and procedural rules that facilitate state regulatory aggression.  In this as in many other respects, globalization presents an opportunity for federalism, rather than a threat to it.  Nothing would be lost if international agreements and obligations were interpreted and enforced to curtail the mischievous state exports of regulatory and tax burdens that we have come to tolerate.  The need to harmonize domestic arrangements with international trade obligations may even prompt us to re-visit and reform, at long last, domestic federalism norms and arrangements that are flatly inconsistent with competitive structures and values.  Our hopelessly dysfunctional and, quite probably, unconstitutional choice-of-law regime would be an excellent place to start.[20]

Globalization is highly unlikely to serve states’-rights values of empowering states.  It may, however, serve the federalist objective of disciplining government at all levels, including the state level.  If that hope makes me a nationalist, then I am a proud nationalist.


 *  John G. Searle Scholar, American Enterprise Institute; Ph.D. (Government), Cornell University, 1987. This paper was presented at “American Sovereignty: Issues for the New Administration and the New Decade,” AEI Conference, April 4, 2001.  A version of this article will appear in The Chicago Journal of International Law.

[1] Edward T. Swaine, “The Undersea World of Foreign Relations Federalism,” at 26.

[2] See, e.g., J. Harvie Wilkinson III, “Federalism and the Future,” 74 So.Cal.L.Rev. 523, 523-24 (2001).

[3] See Crosby v. National Foreign Trade Council, 530 U.S. 363 (2000).

[4] See, e.g., Richard A. Epstein, Simple Rules for a complex world (1995).

[5] For a discussion of OECD policy, see Lubna Kably , “Haven on Earth? You Can Forget it if OECD has its Way,” The Economic Times, November 26, 1999.

[6] See Roberta Romano, the genius of American corporate law (1993).

[7] Bruce Kobayashi & Larry Ribstein, A Recipe for Cookies: State Regulation of Consumer Marketing Information (available at http://www.federalismproject.org ).

[8]  The reverse priority of values—that is, an endorsement of a “civic participation” federalism--probably implies a reverse constitutional presumptions.

[9] Swaine, “Undersea World” at 6.

[10] See Barry R. Weingast, “The Economic Role of Institutions: Market-Preserving Federalism and Economic Development,” 11 J.L. Econ. & Org. 1 (1995); Weingast, “Constitutions as Governance Structures: The Political Foundations of Secure Markets,” 149 J. Institutional & Theoretical Econ. 286 (1993) (describing necessary features of a market-preserving federalism); Jonathan Rodden & Susan Rose-Ackerman, “Does Federalism Preserve Markets?” 83 va. L. Rev. 1521 (1997) (arguing that market-preserving federalism is inherently unstable).

[11] Rodden & Rose Ackerman, supra n. 10.  For my own humble efforts to identify (domestic) political conditions and dynamics that might facilitate competitive federalism see Michael S. Greve, Real Federalism: Why It matters, how it could happen (1999).

[12] The Necessary and Proper Clause, Art. I Sec. 8 Cl. 18, the usual suspect in the search for sources of presumed congressional omnipotence, is not listed in the text because it is not normally viewed as independent grant of power.

[13]  For revisionist arguments that Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.S. 416 (1920) may and should be re-examined see, e.g., Jeremy Rabkin, Why Sovereignty Matters 67-74 (1998); Thomas Healy, Note, “Is Missouri v. Holland Still Good Law? Federalism and the Treaty Power,” 98 Colum. L. Rev. 1726 (1998); and Robert Knowles, “Starbucks and the New Federalism: The Court’s Answer to Globalization,” 95 nw. u. l. rev. 735 (2001).

[14]   See, e.g., Lynn A. Baker, “Conditional Federal Spending After Lopez,” 95 colum. l. rev. 1911 (1995); and Ryan C. Squire, “Effectuating Principles of Federalism: Reevaluating the Federal Spending Power as the Great Tenth Amendment Loophole,” 25 Pepp. L. Rev. 869 (1998).

[15]  See Edward A. Zelinsky, “Unfunded Mandates, Hidden Taxation, and the Tenth Amendment: On Public Choice, Public Interest, and Public Services,” 46 Vand. L. rev. 1355 (1993) (showing that unfounded mandates are response to interest group demands).

[16] The Union of Concerned States does not exist—yet.  The phenomenon of concerted state lobbying on an international stage, however, is already a reality.  See Edward A. Swaine, “Negotiating Federalism: State Bargaining and the Dormant Treaty Power,” 49 duke l. j. 1127, 1130 and sources cited id. n. 7.

[17]   In defense of a larger state role, one might argue that the national government cannot always be relied on to represent the states in international negotiations.  That objection raises large and important questions.  Those questions, however, go to the domestic arrangements concerning the organization and exercise of foreign affairs powers, as distinct from their independent participation on the international stage.

[18] Barclays Bank PLC v. Franchise Tax Bd., 512 U.S. 298 (1994).

[19] See Joseph A. McKinney, created from nafta: the structure, function and significance of the treaty’s related institutions 229-230 (2000) (noting vulnerability of “traditional” areas of state policymaking to international rulemaking and adjudication).

[20] See Douglas Laycock, “Equal Citizens of Equal and Territorial States: The Constitutional Foundations of Choice of Law,” 92 colum. L. rev. 249 (1992).